![]() |
|||||
![]() |
|||||
![]() |
|||||
Strona startowa Foucault Security, Foucault Foucault Reader, Foucault Foucault On Kant, Foucault Foucault Routledge Key Sociologists, Foucault Foucault Routledge Critical Thinkers, Foucault Fabricating Foucault Rationalising the Management of Individuals.EEn, Foucault Foucault Discourse and Truth- The Problematization of Parrhesia (Berkeley, Foucault Formalności po ślubie, First Latin Course, Łacina, Latin - Best, First Latin Course Full Track List, - ⢠M ⤠Sandra Cretu Collection âŹâŹâŹâŹâŹâĄâ¤âŹâŹâŹâŹâŹ, Sandra - Discography Lighting & Studio Albums (1985-2012) |
Foucault and The Birth of Biopolitics, Foucault[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]1 "The Birth of Bio-Politics" – Michel Foucault's Lecture at the Collège de France on Neo-Liberal Governmentality From 1970 until his death in 1984, Michel Foucault held the Chair of "History of Systems of Thought" at the Collège de France. In his public lectures delivered each Wednesday from early January through to the end of March/beginning of April, he reported on his research goals and findings, presenting unpublished material and new conceptual and theoretical research tools. Many of the ideas developed there were later to be taken up in his various book projects. However, he was in fact never to elaborate in writing on some of the research angles he presented there. Foucault's early and unexpected death meant that two of the key series of lectures have remained largely unpublished ever since, namely the lectures held in 1978 ("Sécurité, territoire et population") and in 1979 ("La naissance de la biopolitique"). These lectures focused on the "genealogy of the modern state" (Lect. April 5, 1978/1982b, 43). Foucault deploys the concept of government or "governmentality" as a "guideline" for the analysis he offers by way of historical reconstructions embracing a period starting from Ancient Greek through to modern neo-liberalism (Foucault 1978b, 719). I wish to emphasize two points here, as they seem important for an adequate assessment of the innovative potential of the notion of governmentality. First of all, the concept of governmentality demonstrates Foucault's working hypothesis on the reciprocal constitution of power techniques and forms of knowledge. The semantic linking of governing ("gouverner") and modes of thought ("mentalité") indicates that it is not possible to study the technologies of power without an analysis of the political rationality underpinning them. In other words, there are two sides to governmentality (at certain points Foucault also speaks of "the art of government"). First, the term pin-points a specific form of representation ; government defines a discursive field in which exercising power is "rationalized". This occurs, among other things, by the delineation of concepts, the specification of objects and borders, the provision of arguments and justifications etc. In this manner, government enables a problem to be addressed and offers certain strategies for solving/handling the problem. In this way, it also structures specific 1 The following discussion draws on material of a chapter from my book on Foucault's concept of governmentality (Lemke 1997, pp. 239-56). 2 The version authorized by Foucault contains only the lecture of February 1, 1978 (Foucault 1978) and the summary he prepared of his research findings (Foucault 1997a and 1997b). In addition, there are in part written minutes kept of the lecture of January 31, 1979 (Foucault 1984) and a transcript of the lecture of January 25, 1978 (Foucault 1992). Finally, there is a very incomplete translation into German of the 1978 lecture (Foucault 1982b). The two introductory lectures have been brought out as audio cassettes by Paris publisher Seuil as De la gouvernementalité . Owing to the problematic state of the material, I rely in what follows above all on my own transcriptions from the tape recordings kept in the Fonds Michel Foucault in Paris (Documents C 64, 2-12 and C 67, 1-12). 1 2 forms of intervention . For a political rationality is not pure, neutral knowledge which simply "re-presents" the governing reality; instead, it itself constitutes the intellectual processing of the reality which political technologies can then tackle. This is understood to include agencies, procedures, institutions, legal forms etc. that are intended to enable us to govern the objects and subjects of a political rationality. Second, Foucault uses the concept of government in a comprehensive sense geared strongly to the older meaning of the term and adumbrating the close link between forms of power and processes of subjectification. While the word government today possesses solely a political meaning, Foucault is able to show that up until well into the 18 th century the problem of government was placed in a more general context. Government was a term discussed not only in political tracts, but also in philosophical, religious, medical and pedagogic texts. In addition to control/management by the state or the administration, "government" also signified problems of self-control, guidance for the family and for children, management of the household, directing the soul, etc. For this reason, Foucault defines government as conduct, or, more precisely, as "the conduct of conduct" and thus as a term which ranges from "governing the self" to "governing others". All in all, in his history of governmentality Foucault endeavors to show how the modern sovereign state and the modern autonomous individual co-determine each other's emergence (Lect. Feb. 8, 1978/1982b, 16/17; Foucault, 1982a, 220-1; Senellart, 1995). While in his 1978 lectures Foucault traces the genealogy of governmentality from Classical Greek and Roman days via the early Christian pastoral guidance through to the notion of state reason and the science of the police, the 1979 lectures focused on the study of liberal and neo- liberal forms of government. At the beginning and end of the lecture series, Foucault gave an outline of the classic liberal art of government by discussing the works of Adam Smith, David Hume and Adam Ferguson. In the lectures in-between he analyzed the neo-liberal governmentality, concentrating in particular on two forms of neo-liberalism: German post- War liberalism and the liberalism of the Chicago School, which derives from the former, takes it a step further, and gives it more radical form. Foucault's concept of government has inspired many studies in the social sciences and many historical investigations, and it has been especially his analysis of neo-liberal governmentality that has kindled interest. At the same time, it is precisely this material which has to date remained more or less inaccessible and large parts of which are therefore not widely known. Owing to this difficult starting point, I shall in the first two sections of this article concentrate on this specific section of the lecture series and reproduce in systematic form Foucault's hypotheses on neo-liberal governmentality, citing source material as carefully as possible. In the concluding section I shall offer a short discussion of the methodological and theoretical principles underlying the concept of governmentality and the critical political angle it provides for an analysis of neo-liberalism, followed by a brief presentation of some subsequent work inspired by Foucault's account. 3 In part of the lecture of March 7, 1979 Foucault also concerned himself with French neo- liberalism and the politics of President Giscard d'Estaing. 2 3 1. "Inequality is equal for all": the Ordo-liberals The theoretical foundations for German post-War liberalism were drawn up by jurists and economists who in the years 1928-1930 had belonged to the "Freiburg School" or had been associated with it and later published in the journal Ordo . Notable among them were Wilhelm Röpke, Walter Eucken, Franz Böhm, Alexander Rüstow, Alfred Müller-Armack and others. These Ordo-liberals played a substantial role in devising the "social market economy" and decisively influenced the principles of economic policy applied in West Germany in its infancy (see 1997b, 77-79). Foucault puts his finger on a series of issues and experiences of the "Freiburg School" which it shared with the "Frankfurt School". The two had in common not only the point in time when they first appeared on the scholarly scene — namely the mid-1920s — and a destiny shaped by exile, but both were also part and parcel of a political-academic problematic which prevailed in Germany as of the early 1920s and was closely associated with Max Weber. Weber was important for having shifted Marx's problem of the contradictory logic of capitalism onto a level where he discussed it as the irrational rationality of capitalist society. This problem was the point of departure for both schools, but resulted in completely different angles of discussion: The Frankfurt School searched for a new social rationality that would annul and overcome the irrationality of the capitalist economy. The Freiburg School opted for the opposite approach and endeavored to re-define the economic (capitalist) rationality in order to prevent the social irrationality of capitalism from unfolding (Lect. Feb. 7, 1979). Foucault believes that another parallel of both schools is the significance accorded to reflection on the reasons for the emergence of the Nazis. Yet here, too, addressing one and the same problem leads to two diametrically opposite answers. While Adorno, Horkheimer and other Critical theorists insist that there is a causal connection between capitalism and fascism, the neo-liberals consider the Third Reich not to be the product of liberalism but instead the result of an absence of liberalism. The collapse of democracy in Germany is not caused by a functioning market economy, but rather the consequence of the fact that such an economy did not exist. From the viewpoint of the Ordo-liberals, the Third Reich was the inevitable result of a series of anti-liberal policies. Unlike the Frankfurt School, the Freiburg School therefore believed that the crucial alternative was not between capitalism and socialism, but between liberalism and different forms of state interventionism (Soviet socialism, National socialism, Keynesianism), all of which, if to differing degrees, threaten liberty (Lect. Feb. 7, 1979; Burchell, 1993, 270). Now, Foucault maintains that the theoretical basis for the Ordo-liberals' conviction was their radical anti-naturalistic conception of the market and of the principle of competition. In the Ordo-liberal scheme, the market does not amount to a natural economic reality, with intrinsic laws which the art of government must bear in mind and respect; instead, the market can only be constituted and kept alive by dint of political interventions. In this view, like the market, competition, too, is not a natural fact always already part and parcel of the economic domain. Instead, this fundamental economic mechanism can only function if support is 3 4 forthcoming to bolster a series of conditions, and adherence to the latter must consistently be guaranteed by legal measures. Pure competition is therefore neither something that exists "naturally", nor is it something ever completely attained, but provides the justifications for a projected target which necessitated incessant and active politics. In such an approach there is no room for a conception that distinguishes between a limited domain of liberty and the legitimate domain of government intervention. Unlike this negative conception of the state typical of liberal theory in the 18 th and 19 th century, in the Ordo-liberal view, the market mechanism and the impact of competition can only arise if they are produced by the practice of government. The Ordo-liberals believe that the state and the market economy are not juxtaposed to each other but that the one mutually presumes the existence of the other (Lect. Feb. 7, 1979). Foucault emphasizes three important strategic functions of this anti-naturalism: 1. It initially means in theoretical terms that the strict separation between an economic base and a political-legal superstructure is inappropriate. This dichotomy is therefore not tenable because the economy is not a domain of natural mechanism, but instead defines a social field of regulated practices. 2. The historical significance of this hypothesis is that it rejects a concept of history that attempts to derive socio-political changes from the economic transformation processes of capitalism. For the Ordo-liberals, the history of capitalism is an economic-institutional history. It is not a unilateral causal connection structuring the course of history but incessant reciprocity: capitalism is an "historical figure" through which economic processes and institutional "framework" are articulated, refer to and support each other. 3. The political dimension of this hypothesis addresses the survival of capitalism. For the Ordo-liberals there is no capitalism because there is no logic to capital. What is called capitalism is not the product of a pure economic process and historical capitalism cannot be derived from a "logic of capital". We do not have to do here with a firmly circumscribed and defined structure ( capitalism which possesses an end we can forecast owing to its contradictory logic) but instead with something that is historically singular ( one form of capitalism among possible other forms). In other words, we have to do with something which is open for a specific number of economic and institutional variables and operates in a field of possibilities: a "capitalist system". Thus, the focus of theoretical debate is on the fact that capitalism is a construct: If capitalism is an economic-institutional unity, then we must be able to intervene in this ensemble in such a way that in one and the same process we both change capitalism and "invent" ("intervenir"/"inventir") a new capitalism. From this angle, we consider less an existing form of capitalism and instead try and create a new one. The Ordo- liberals replace the conception of the economy as a domain of autonomous rules and laws by a concept of "economic order" (Foucault uses the original German term "Wirtschaftsordnung") as an object of social intervention and political regulation (Lect. Feb. 20, 1979). This form of argumentation also emerges in the way the Ordo-liberals tackled two positions which believed capitalism was unable to be innovative owing to its intrinsic regularities. On the one hand, the Ordo-liberals reject Schumpeter's pessimistic assertion that capitalism necessarily exhibits monopolistic tendencies. They admittedly agree with him that 4 5 ongoing concentration is not attributable to the economic process itself, but stems from the social consequences of competitions: both Schumpeter and the Ordo-liberals construe the monopolistic organization not as an economic but as a social phenomenon. However, the Ordo-liberals draw completely different conclusions from this shared appraisal. Precisely because monopolization is a social phenomenon, they suggest, it is not some irrevocable and inevitable process, but can be prevented by social intervention and by creating a commensurate institutional framework. Monopolization is not some economic destiny, but the result of a failed political strategy and inadequate forms of institutionalization (Lect. Feb. 20, 1979). On the other hand, the Ordo-liberals attack Sombart's proposal that innate to the modern economy is an irreversible development into a uniform "mass society" which leads to the immiseration of human relations and the experience of community gives way increasingly to anonymous social relations. The Ordo-liberals again take the opposite track. They hold that it is not capitalism which is responsible for the problems outlined by Sombart and others, but claim that instead it is the product of the planning methods and bureaucratic apparatuses deployed by enemies of the market mechanism. From this viewpoint, the neo-liberal art of rulership does not spawn a uniform society but instead represents a new direction intended to lead directly away from the homogenizing trends of a "mass society" (Lect. Feb. 14, 1979; Gordon, 1986, 80-1). If we follow Foucault's interpretation, then the Ordo-liberals' theoretical efforts were designed to show, in the wake of the experience of the Third Reich, that the irrationalities and dysfunctionalities of capitalist society could be overcome by politico-institutional "inventions", as these problems were not compellingly innate to the logic of capitalism but of a contingent historical nature. For this reason, the Ordo-liberals change the theoretical angle, construing the economy not in naturalistic but in institutionalist terms. Under such conditions, it is no longer meaningful to speak of the destructive "logic of capital", as such talk assumes the existence of an autonomous domain of the economy with its own rules and limits. The Ordo-liberals instead presume that the survival of the "capitalist system" depends on the political capacity to construct innovative answers to the more or less contingent structural compulsions and blockages that are part of this system and which it is necessarily subject to. To put it over tersely, the Ordo-liberals try to show that there is not just one capitalism with its logic, its dead-ends, and its contradictions, but an economic-institutional entity which is historically open and can be changed politically. Such a conception of the economic domain includes the necessity of devising a social policy (Foucault uses the original German term "Gesellschaftspolitik") which is not limited to transferring and redistributing monies but stands out for its active creation of the historical and social conditions for the market. For the Ordo-liberals, social policy did not exercise a negative, compensatory function; moreover, its task, they believed, was not to offset the destructive impact of economic liberty. Instead of lessening the anti-social consequences of competition, it had to block the anti-competitive mechanisms which society can spawn. There are two important strands to such a social policy, namely the universalization of the entrepreneurial form, and the re-definition of law. 5 [ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ] |
||||
![]() |
|||||
Wszelkie Prawa Zastrzeżone! Jedyną nadzieją jest... nadzieja. Design by SZABLONY.maniak.pl. |
![]() |
||||
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |